Eros And Civilization.pdf

(149 KB) Pobierz
<!DOCTYPE html PUBLIC "-//W3C//DTD HTML 4.01//EN" "http://www.w3.org/TR/html4/strict.dtd">
Vol. 12 No. 1
© 1999 SAGE Publications ( London, Thousand Oaks and New Delhi)
pp. 73–90
[0952-6951(199902)12:1;73-90; 007788]
Eros and Civilization revisited
PETER M. R. STIRK
A BSTRACT
The article consists of a re-examination of Marcuse’s Eros and Civiliz-
ation in the light of continuing interest in that work. After a brief con-
sideration of Marcuse’s attempt to use Freud to indict contemporary
civilization, focusing on the concepts of surplus repression and guilt,
the article turns to his utopian sketch of Eros as a culture builder and
the reconciliation of reason and instinct. These themes, which form the
focus of recent interest, are explored by examining Marcuse’s interpre-
tation of Kant and Schiller as well as Freud. In all cases Marcuse’s
interpretation is shown to be flawed. The conclusion is that Marcuse’s
attempt to indict established reason in the light of instinct and yet to
hold out the prospect of a reconciliation of reason and instinct leads to
an impoverished concept of both.
Key words critical theory, Freud, Marcuse, philosophy, psychology
Eros and Civilization was Herbert Marcuse’s most provocative book. The
contentious interpretation of Freud, the general thesis, namely that a society
pervaded by Eros was within the grasp of men, as well as the celebration of
‘polymorphous perversity’ and many other details of interpretation, all con-
tributed to its status as a radically utopian work. Over 20 years later Jürgen
Habermas recalled the ‘stunning impression’ of Marcuse’s exposition of his
ideas in a lecture on Freud in 1956. For Habermas and his fellow research
assistants in the Institute for Social Research ‘this was the moment when we
first faced an embodiment and vivid expression of the political spirit of the
old Frankfurt School’ (Habermas, 1985: 68; see also Dews, 1992: 206–7).
Despite the numerous and often telling criticisms of Eros and Civilization ,
854335748.005.png 854335748.006.png 854335748.007.png
 
74
HISTORY OF THE HUMAN SCIENCES
12(1)
it has continued to exert a certain fascination, partly in its own right and partly
because of a revival of interest in Erich Fromm. It has naturally been of
concern in the surveys of Marcuse’s thought, though these do not show any
consensus about its validity and wider significance (Flego and Schmied-
Kowarzik, 1989; Geohagen, 1981; Institut für Sozialforschung, 1992; Katz,
1982; Kellner, 1984; Pippin, 1988; Schoolman, 1980). Indeed the editors of one
volume drew attention to the growing divergence in attitudes to Eros and
Civilization , ranging from outright dismissal to enthusiastic assertions of its
contemporary relevance (Flego and Schmied-Kowarzik, 1989: 7–8). It also
figures prominently in some approaches to Freud and in works concerned
with the relation between critical theory and psychology, again with no
evident consensus (Jacoby, 1975; Ricoeur, 1970; Whitebook, 1995; White-
book, 1996). The revival of interest in the ideas of Fromm, whose supporters
claim he has been unjustly neglected, in part at least as a result of the accu-
sation levelled at him by Marcuse, has also contributed to persistent interest
in Eros and Civilization (Bronner, 1994; Burston, 1991; Erich-Fromm-
Gesellschaft, 1991; Funk, 1980; Rickert, 1986). Like Marcuse, Fromm had
been a member of the Frankfurt School. He had, however, parted, amid some
animosity, in 1939 (Horkheimer, 1995: 666–7). Fromm’s revision of Freudian
theory came under attack from Marcuse in an article in Dissent shortly before
the publication of Eros and Civilization . The polemic between Marcuse and
Fromm, the ground for which had been laid earlier, helps to explain, if not
justify, Marcuse’s sometimes obdurate defence of Freud. Marcuse’s avowed
concern was ‘not with a corrected or improved interpretation of Freudian
concepts but with their philosophical and sociological implications’ (Marcuse,
1969: 25). 1 By constantly insisting upon denial of gratification, the repression
of instincts for the sake of ‘civilization’, Freud’s theory was an indictment of
existing civilization. In Marcuse’s eyes, Fromm’s revisionism, the rejection of
Freud’s theory of instincts, called into question ‘a radically critical theory’ and
was, by that very fact, suspect (Marcuse, 1969: 167).
The polemic against Fromm and other revisionists forms part of the back-
ground to Eros and Civilization , but only part. Also essential to under-
standing Marcuse’s stance in Eros and Civilization is his advocacy of
hedonism, which pre-dated any sustained interest in Freud. His essay of
1938, ‘On Hedonism’, criticized the disparagement of sensual pleasure but at
the same time claimed that ‘The designation of happiness as the condition of
the comprehensive gratification of the individual’s needs and wants is abstract
and incorrect as long as it accepts needs and wants as ultimate data in their
present form’ (Marcuse, 1968: 189).
The third element to the background to Eros and Civilization was, of
course, the patent absence of any revolutionary impulse in the western world
after the Second World War. Along with his colleagues in the Institute for
Social Research he had taken it as axiomatic that the productive capacities of
854335748.001.png
‘EROS AND CIVILIZATION’ REVISITED
75
modern, capitalist societies had developed to such an extent that a radically
different type of society was possible. They further assumed that this should
have been evident to all and that if it was not some explanation had to be
found for why the anticipated insight into the possibility and desirability of
a new type of society had been blocked (Marcuse, 1969: 11). 2 The questions
underlying Eros and Civilization were really those bequeathed by Marx:
How do we know when a mode of production is obsolete? Why should men
recognize this obsolescence? Why should they act on that insight and abolish
that mode of production? Turning to Freud for an answer to these questions
was not the most obvious strategy. Earlier, in ‘On Hedonism’, he had
remained on more traditional socialist ground and had argued that ‘only
those groups with the greatest purchasing power can take advantage of the
expanded capacities [provided by modern technology] and their gratification’
(Marcuse, 1968: 184). But this made no sense against the backcloth of the
post-war affluent society. Worse still the affluent society was also a more per-
missive one. As he acknowledged in 1966 ‘it made no sense to talk about
surplus repression when men and women enjoy more sexual liberty than ever
before’ (Marcuse, 1969: 12). 3 But talk about it he did.
These issues, the often bitter dispute over the status of Freud’s theories, the
significance of hedonism in affluent and permissive societies, the problem of
how to sustain a radical critique of society with revolutionary ambitions in
an age in which radical social movements and utopian perspectives had dis-
appeared from the agenda, all help to explain the initial impact and continued
interest in Eros and Civilization , as well as Marcuse’s own motives and style.
This article, however, is concerned to assess Marcuse’s arguments and to do
so by measuring the claims he makes against his own sources. It seeks to
proceed through an immanent critique, which he and the other members of
the Institute for Social Research held up as their own preferred method.
Surplus repression played a key role in Marcuse’s argument. It was this
which allowed him to assert the obsolescence of current society. Surplus
repression was defined as follows: ‘the restrictions necessitated by social
domination. This is distinguished from (basic) repression : the “modification”
of the instincts necessary for the perpetuations of the human race in civiliz-
ation’ (Marcuse, 1969: 42). The distinction between basic and surplus repres-
sion has induced much dubious speculation on analogies with Marxian
concepts. According to Morton Schoolman Marcuse’s concepts of basic and
surplus repression are extrapolations from Marx’s socially necessary and
surplus labour (Schoolman, 1980: 94–5; see also Kellner, 1984: 164). But this
is wrong. The problem with surplus labour for Marx is not that it exists. The
problem is that its product is expropriated by capitalists. The problem with
surplus repression for Marcuse is that it exists at all. The point is to abolish it.
There is, however, one useful thing to emerge from the comparison with
Marx’s concepts. Surplus labour is, in principle, measurable. At least it was
854335748.002.png
76
HISTORY OF THE HUMAN SCIENCES
12(1)
in the abstract models in which Marx introduced the concept. Can the same
be said for surplus repression? It is important that it can, for it is surplus
repression alone which has to be abolished. Moreover, the concept of surplus
repression promised to provide a solution to another problem, that is, how
can we talk about surplus repression in a more permissive and affluent
society? According to Marcuse, ‘[t]he same and even a reduced scope of
instinctual regimentation would constitute a higher degree of repression at a
mature stage of civilization’ (Marcuse, 1969: 74). From this perspective even
the affluent and permissive society could be repressive, and even more repres-
sive than less affluent and less permissive stages of civilization. If the gap
between the level of repression required, given the level of economic develop-
ment, and that actually operative grew, the more mature stage would be more
repressive. At one point Marcuse seemed to find an answer. He picked up
two distinct themes in Freud. The first was the idea that sexual instincts were
inimical to civilization and had to be repressed. The second was that there
was an erotic component to society. Seizing upon the apparent ambiguity he
proclaimed that ‘the free Eros does not preclude lasting civilized societal
relationships ... it repels only the supra-repressive organization of societal
relationships’ (Marcuse, 1969: 46–7).
Marcuse wanted an instinct, Eros, to discriminate. It is, indeed, possible to
talk of instinctual discrimination between all kinds of things. But not in this
case. Marcuse required discrimination between necessary and surplus repres-
sion, where what is necessary and what is surplus are, at his own insistence,
historically variable. Although he repeated the assertion that Eros could dis-
criminate in the way required, he did not develop the suggestion in any detail
(see Rotenstreich, 1970: 46–7). Indeed, he may have been aware of the weak-
ness of the idea for he reverted to a more prosaic position. At the end Marcuse
was reduced to asserting that everyone would recognize, consciously, the dis-
tinction, were they not prevented from doing so. But that was merely to go
back to the starting-point. Instinct had not been able to provide a substitute
for insight but the insight was stubbornly absent.
An alternative was to try to find some other psychological index of the
repressiveness of society. An obvious candidate was guilt. Indeed in recent
interpretations Marcuse’s account of guilt has been singled out for praise
(Schmid-Noerr, 1990: 206). In the lecture which inspired Habermas, Marcuse
declared that ‘This is Freud’s revolutionary insight: the conflict ... between
the reality of repression and the almost equally real possibility of doing away
with repression’ (Marcuse, 1970a: 18). It was precisely this which was sup-
posed to account for the feeling of guilt. Guilt was not merely internalized
repression but was also ‘guilt about a freedom that one has both missed and
betrayed’ (Marcuse, 1970a: 18). One would expect that this would lead
Marcuse to argue that the feeling of guilt had increased parallel with the possi-
bility of putting an end to repression. Indeed, he did. He was able to quote
854335748.003.png
‘EROS AND CIVILIZATION’ REVISITED
77
Freud speculating upon the increase of guilt to the point ‘perhaps ... that
individuals can hardly support’ (Marcuse, 1969: 70). But for Freud this had
nothing to do with the possibility of putting an end to repression. Accord-
ing to Freud’s speculation, guilt increased because, in some opaque way, the
conflicts within the family that first led to the feeling of guilt, were repeated
as the community was extended beyond the family. Hence, the wider the
community the greater the feeling of guilt. It is ironic that Marcuse quoted
the very passage in which Freud said this, for he was then obliged to lament
that ‘the change in the quality of guiltiness, its growing irrationality, seems
to disappear’ (Marcuse, 1969: 70). . If Marcuse had followed through the line
of Freud’s speculation the incompatibility between his interpretation and
Freud’s would have become even clearer. For when Freud suggested there
might be a ‘cultural super-ego’ whose excessive demands threatened to
produce ‘neurotic’ civilizations he did not bemoan the renunciation of gratifi-
cation. Instead he quoted the Christian injunction to ‘Love thy neighbour as
thyself’ in order to denounce it as incompatible with the egoism of human
nature (Freud, 1975: 80). 4
The dubious interpretation of Freud would not matter if Marcuse had been
able to find other support for his contention that there was a feeling of guilt
which could be tied to his postulation of ‘surplus repression’. But this he
could not do. He did seek to deploy other Freudian models to explain why
men did not rebel. There, however, he took it for granted that rebellion was
warranted, that the obsolescence of the existing socioeconomic order would
have been evident were it not for the mechanisms that blocked this insight. 5
All he could do beyond this, was to point to the well-known horrors of the
20th century and denounce the destructiveness of modern civilization.
This weakness may well explain why the distinction between basic and
surplus repression now receives cursory attention, where it is noted at all. It
is not the appropriation of Freud as part of a, ultimately Marxian, theory of
revolution that now holds centre stage, but the appropriation of Freud as part
of a utopian sketch. Marcuse’s utopia, as outlined in Eros and Civilization,
rested on two related claims. The first was the general point that ‘the free Eros
does not preclude lasting civilized societal relationships’ (Marcuse, 1969: 46).
Here all Marcuse had to do was to demonstrate that men were not inherently
anti-social beings. The second was the more specific claim that there was a
‘libidinous morality’. This is a much more demanding assertion. Here it was
not sufficient to prove that the contours of ‘civilized societal relationships’
could be discerned in the instincts.
The compatibility of Eros and civilization was defended on two levels.
First, Marcuse claimed that Freud’s psychology was an adequate basis for
sketching his utopia. This was bound up with his hostility to the revisionists
who claimed that Freud’s theories had to be corrected or supplemented by
social and cultural factors. Ironically though, in his strongest formulation of
854335748.004.png
Zgłoś jeśli naruszono regulamin